Jump to content

Cardinality

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Cardinalities)
The set of all Platonic solids has 5 elements. Thus the cardinality of is 5 or, written symbolically, .

In mathematics, cardinality describes a relationship between sets which compares their relative size.[1] For example, the sets and are the same size as they each contain 3 elements. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized to infinite sets, which allows one to distinguish between different types of infinity, and to perform arithmetic on them. There are two notions often used when referring to cardinality: one which compares sets directly using bijections and injections, and another which uses cardinal numbers.[2] The cardinality of a set may also be called its size, when no confusion with other notions of size is possible.[a]

When two sets, and , have the same cardinality, it is usually written as ; however, if referring to the cardinal number of an individual set , it is simply denoted , with a vertical bar on each side;[3] this is the same notation as absolute value, and the meaning depends on context. The cardinal number of a set may alternatively be denoted by , , , or .

History

[edit]

A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.[4] Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as 40000 years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.[5] The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian mathematics and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.[6]

From the 6th century BCE, the writings of Greek philosophers show hints of the cardinality of infinite sets. While they considered the notion of infinity as an endless series of actions, such as adding 1 to a number repeatedly, they did not consider the size of an infinite set of numbers to be a thing.[7] The ancient Greek notion of infinity also considered the division of things into parts repeated without limit. In Euclid's Elements, commensurability was described as the ability to compare the length of two line segments, a and b, as a ratio, as long as there were a third segment, no matter how small, that could be laid end-to-end a whole number of times into both a and b. But with the discovery of irrational numbers, it was seen that even the infinite set of all rational numbers was not enough to describe the length of every possible line segment.[8] Still, there was no concept of infinite sets as something that had cardinality.

To better understand infinite sets, a notion of cardinality was formulated c. 1880 by Georg Cantor, the originator of set theory. He examined the process of equating two sets with bijection, a one-to-one correspondence between the elements of two sets based on a unique relationship. In 1891, with the publication of Cantor's diagonal argument, he demonstrated that there are sets of numbers that cannot be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers, i.e. uncountable sets that contain more elements than there are in the infinite set of natural numbers.[9]

Comparing sets

[edit]
Bijective function from N to the set E of even numbers. Although E is a proper subset of N, both sets have the same cardinality.
N does not have the same cardinality as its power set P(N): For every function f from N to P(N), the set T = {nN: nf(n)} disagrees with every set in the range of f, hence f cannot be surjective. The picture shows an example f and the corresponding T; red: nf(n)\T, blue:nT\f(n).

While the cardinality of a finite set is simply comparable to its number of elements, extending the notion to infinite sets usually starts with defining the notion of comparison of arbitrary sets (some of which are possibly infinite).

Definition 1: |A| = |B|

[edit]

Two sets have the same cardinality if there exists a bijection (a.k.a., one-to-one correspondence) from to ,[10] that is, a function from to that is both injective and surjective. Such sets are said to be equipotent, equipollent, or equinumerous.

For example, the set of non-negative even numbers has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers, since the function is a bijection from to (see picture).

For finite sets and , if some bijection exists from to , then each injective or surjective function from to is a bijection. This is no longer true for infinite and . For example, the function from to , defined by is injective, but not surjective since 2, for instance, is not mapped to, and from to , defined by (see: modulo operation) is surjective, but not injective, since 0 and 1 for instance both map to 0. Neither nor can challenge , which was established by the existence of .

Definition 2: |A| ≤ |B|

[edit]

has cardinality less than or equal to the cardinality of , if there exists an injective function from into .

If and , then (a fact known as Schröder–Bernstein theorem). The axiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that or for every and .[11][12]

Definition 3: |A| < |B|

[edit]

has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality of , if there is an injective function, but no bijective function, from to .

For example, the set of all natural numbers has cardinality strictly less than its power set , because is an injective function from to , and it can be shown that no function from to can be bijective (see picture). By a similar argument, has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality of the set of all real numbers. For proofs, see Cantor's diagonal argument or Cantor's first uncountability proof.

Cardinal numbers

[edit]

In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined functionally. In other words, it was not defined as a specific object itself. However, such an object can be defined as follows.

The relation of having the same cardinality is called equinumerosity, and this is an equivalence relation on the class of all sets. The equivalence class of a set A under this relation, then, consists of all those sets which have the same cardinality as A. There are two ways to define the "cardinality of a set":

  1. The cardinality of a set A is defined as its equivalence class under equinumerosity.
  2. A representative set is designated for each equivalence class. The most common choice is the initial ordinal in that class. This is usually taken as the definition of cardinal number in axiomatic set theory.

Assuming the axiom of choice, the cardinalities of the infinite sets are denoted

For each ordinal , is the least cardinal number greater than .

The cardinality of the natural numbers is denoted aleph-null (), while the cardinality of the real numbers is denoted by "" (a lowercase fraktur script "c"), and is also referred to as the cardinality of the continuum. Cantor showed, using the diagonal argument, that . We can show that , this also being the cardinality of the set of all subsets of the natural numbers.

The continuum hypothesis says that , i.e. is the smallest cardinal number bigger than , i.e. there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis is independent of ZFC, a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is consistent. For more detail, see § Cardinality of the continuum below.[13][14][15]

Finite, countable and uncountable sets

[edit]

If the axiom of choice holds, the law of trichotomy holds for cardinality. Thus we can make the following definitions:

  • Any set X with cardinality less than that of the natural numbers, or | X | < | N |, is said to be a finite set.
  • Any set X that has the same cardinality as the set of the natural numbers, or | X | = | N | = , is said to be a countably infinite set.[10]
  • Any set X with cardinality greater than that of the natural numbers, or | X | > | N |, for example | R | = > | N |, is said to be uncountable.

Infinite sets

[edit]

Our intuition gained from finite sets breaks down when dealing with infinite sets. In the late 19th century Georg Cantor, Gottlob Frege, Richard Dedekind and others rejected the view that the whole cannot be the same size as the part.[16][citation needed] One example of this is Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel. Indeed, Dedekind defined an infinite set as one that can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with a strict subset (that is, having the same size in Cantor's sense); this notion of infinity is called Dedekind infinite. Cantor introduced the cardinal numbers, and showed—according to his bijection-based definition of size—that some infinite sets are greater than others. The smallest infinite cardinality is that of the natural numbers ().

Cardinality of the continuum

[edit]

One of Cantor's most important results was that the cardinality of the continuum () is greater than that of the natural numbers (); that is, there are more real numbers R than natural numbers N. Namely, Cantor showed that (see Beth one) satisfies:

(see Cantor's diagonal argument or Cantor's first uncountability proof).

The continuum hypothesis states that there is no cardinal number between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers, that is,

However, this hypothesis can neither be proved nor disproved within the widely accepted ZFC axiomatic set theory, if ZFC is consistent.

Cardinal arithmetic can be used to show not only that the number of points in a real number line is equal to the number of points in any segment of that line, but that this is equal to the number of points on a plane and, indeed, in any finite-dimensional space. These results are highly counterintuitive, because they imply that there exist proper subsets and proper supersets of an infinite set S that have the same size as S, although S contains elements that do not belong to its subsets, and the supersets of S contain elements that are not included in it.

The first of these results is apparent by considering, for instance, the tangent function, which provides a one-to-one correspondence between the interval (−½π, ½π) and R (see also Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel).

The second result was first demonstrated by Cantor in 1878, but it became more apparent in 1890, when Giuseppe Peano introduced the space-filling curves, curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square, or cube, or hypercube, or finite-dimensional space. These curves are not a direct proof that a line has the same number of points as a finite-dimensional space, but they can be used to obtain such a proof.

Cantor also showed that sets with cardinality strictly greater than exist (see his generalized diagonal argument and theorem). They include, for instance:

  • the set of all subsets of R, i.e., the power set of R, written P(R) or 2R
  • the set RR of all functions from R to R

Both have cardinality

(see Beth two).

The cardinal equalities and can be demonstrated using cardinal arithmetic:

Examples and properties

[edit]
  • If X = {a, b, c} and Y = {apples, oranges, peaches}, where a, b, and c are distinct, then | X | = | Y | because { (a, apples), (b, oranges), (c, peaches)} is a bijection between the sets X and Y. The cardinality of each of X and Y is 3.
  • If | X | ≤ | Y |, then there exists Z such that | X | = | Z | and ZY.
  • If | X | ≤ | Y | and | Y | ≤ | X |, then | X | = | Y |. This holds even for infinite cardinals, and is known as Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem.
  • Sets with cardinality of the continuum include the set of all real numbers, the set of all irrational numbers and the interval .

Union and intersection

[edit]

If A and B are disjoint sets, then

From this, one can show that in general, the cardinalities of unions and intersections are related by the following equation:[17]

Definition of cardinality in class theory (NBG or MK)

[edit]

Here denote a class of all sets, and denotes the class of all ordinal numbers.

We use the intersection of a class which is defined by , therefore . In this case

.

This definition allows also obtain a cardinality of any proper class , in particular

This definition is natural since it agrees with the axiom of limitation of size which implies bijection between and any proper class.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Stoll, Robert R. (1963). Set Theory and Logic. San Francisco, CA: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-63829-4.
  2. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Cardinal Number". MathWorld.
  3. ^ "Cardinality | Brilliant Math & Science Wiki". brilliant.org. Retrieved 2020-08-23.
  4. ^ Cepelewicz, Jordana Animals Count and Use Zero. How Far Does Their Number Sense Go?, Quanta, August 9, 2021
  5. ^ "Early Human Counting Tools". Math Timeline. Retrieved 2018-04-26.
  6. ^ Duncan J. Melville (2003). Third Millennium Chronology Archived 2018-07-07 at the Wayback Machine, Third Millennium Mathematics. St. Lawrence University.
  7. ^ Allen, Donald (2003). "The History of Infinity" (PDF). Texas A&M Mathematics. Archived from the original (PDF) on August 1, 2020. Retrieved Nov 15, 2019.
  8. ^ Kurt Von Fritz (1945). "The Discovery of Incommensurability by Hippasus of Metapontum". The Annals of Mathematics.
  9. ^ Georg Cantor (1891). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre" (PDF). Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 1: 75–78.
  10. ^ a b "Infinite Sets and Cardinality". Mathematics LibreTexts. 2019-12-05. Retrieved 2020-08-23.
  11. ^ Friedrich M. Hartogs (1915), Felix Klein; Walther von Dyck; David Hilbert; Otto Blumenthal (eds.), "Über das Problem der Wohlordnung", Mathematische Annalen, 76 (4), Leipzig: B. G. Teubner: 438–443, doi:10.1007/bf01458215, ISSN 0025-5831, S2CID 121598654
  12. ^ Felix Hausdorff (2002), Egbert Brieskorn; Srishti D. Chatterji; et al. (eds.), Grundzüge der Mengenlehre (1. ed.), Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, p. 587, ISBN 3-540-42224-2 - Original edition (1914)
  13. ^ Cohen, Paul J. (December 15, 1963). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 50 (6): 1143–1148. Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C. doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143. JSTOR 71858. PMC 221287. PMID 16578557.
  14. ^ Cohen, Paul J. (January 15, 1964). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 51 (1): 105–110. Bibcode:1964PNAS...51..105C. doi:10.1073/pnas.51.1.105. JSTOR 72252. PMC 300611. PMID 16591132.
  15. ^ Penrose, R (2005), The Road to Reality: A Complete guide to the Laws of the Universe, Vintage Books, ISBN 0-09-944068-7
  16. ^ Georg Cantor (1887), "Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten", Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 91: 81–125
    Reprinted in: Georg Cantor (1932), Adolf Fraenkel (Lebenslauf); Ernst Zermelo (eds.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, pp. 378–439 Here: p.413 bottom
  17. ^ Applied Abstract Algebra, K.H. Kim, F.W. Roush, Ellis Horwood Series, 1983, ISBN 0-85312-612-7 (student edition), ISBN 0-85312-563-5 (library edition)
  1. ^ Such as length and area in geometry. – A line of finite length is a set of points that has infinite cardinality.